Zizek Slavoj
Organs without bodies: Deleuze and consequences
Ц New York, London: Routledge, 2004. Ц 217 p.
Contents
Introduction: An Encounter, Not a Dialogue
DELEUZE
The Reality of the Virtual
Becoming versus History
"Becoming-Machine"
Un jour, peut-etre, le siecle sera empiriomoniste?
Quasi-Cause
Is It Possible Not to Love Spinoza?
Kant, Hegel
Hegel 1: Taking Deleuze from Behind
Hegel 2: From Epistemology to Ontology ... and Back
Hegel 3: The Minimal Difference
The Torsion of Meaning
A Comic Hegelian Interlude: Dumb and Dumber
The Becoming-Oedipal of Deleuze
Phallus
Fantasy
RIS
CONSEQUENCES
Science: Cognitivism with Freud
"Autopoiesis"
Memes, Memes Everywhere
Against Hyphen-Ethics
Cognitive Closure?
"Little Jolts of Enjoyment"
[3]
The Reality of the Virtual
The measure of
the true love for a philosopher is that one recognizes traces of his concepts all around in one's daily
experience. Recently, while watching again Sergei Eisenstein's Ivan the
Terrible, I noticed a wonderful detail in the coronation scene at the beginning of the first part: when
the two (for the time
being) closest friends of Ivan pour golden coins from the large plates onto his newly anointed head,
this veritable rain of gold cannot but surprise the spectator by its magically
excessive characterЧ even after we see the two plates almost empty, we cut to Ivan's head on which golden coins
"nonrealistically" continue to pour in a continuing flow. Is this excess not very
"Deleuzian"? Is it not the excess of the pure flow of becoming over
its corporeal cause, of the virtual over the actual? The first determination that comes to mind
apropos of Deleuze is that he is the philosopher of the VirtualЧand the first reaction to it should
be to oppose
Deleuze's notion of the Virtual to the all-pervasive topic of virtual reality: what matters to
Deleuze is not virtual reality but the reality of the virtual (which, in Lacanian terms, is the
Real). Virtual Reality in itself is a rather miserable idea: that of imitating
reality, of reproducing its experience in an artificial medium. The reality of
the Virtual, on the other hand,
stands for the reality of the Virtual as such, for its real effects and consequences. Let us take an
attractor in mathematics: all positive lines or points in its sphere of attraction
only approach it in an endless fashion, never reaching its formЧthe existence of this form is purely virtual, being nothing more than
the shape toward which lines and points tend. However, precisely as such, the virtual
is the Real of this field: the immovable focal point around which all elements circulate. Is not this Virtual ultimately the Symbolic
as such? Let us take symbolic authority: to function as an effective authority, it has
to remain not-fully-actualized, an eternal threat.
[4]
Perhaps, the ontological
difference between the Virtual and the Acнtual is best captured by the shift in
the way quantum physics conceives of the relationship between particles and
their interactions: in an initial moment, it appears as if first
(ontologically, at least) there are particles interacting in the mode of waves, oscillations,
and so forth; then, in a second moment, we are forced to enact a radical shift of perspectiveЧ
the primordial ontological fact are the waves themselves (trajectories, oscillations), and particles are nothing but the nodal
points in which different waves intersect.[1]
This brings us to the constitutive ambiguity of the relationship between actual and virtual: (1) the human eye reduces
the perception of light; it
actualizes light in a certain way (perceiving certain colors, etc.), a rose in a different way, a bat
in a different way.... The flow of
light "in itself" is nothing actual, but, rather, the pure virtuality
of infiнnite possibilities actualized in a multitude of ways; (2) on the other
hand, the human eye expands
perceptionЧit inscribes what it "really sees" into the
intricate network of memories and anticipations (like Proust with the taste of madeleine), it can develop new
perceptions, and so forth.[2]
The genius of
Deleuze resides in his notion of "transcendental emнpiricism": in contrast to
the standard notion of the transcendental as the formal conceptual network that structures the
rich flow of empirical data, the Deleuzian "transcendental" is infinitely RICHER than
realityЧit is the infinite potential field of
virtualities out of which reality is actualized. The term "transcendental" is used here
in the strict philosophical sense of the a priori conditions of possibility of our experience of constituted
realнity. The paradoxical
coupling of opposites (transcendental + empirical) points toward a field of experience beyond (or,
rather, beneath) the experience of constituted or perceived reality.
[5]
We remain
here within the field of
consciousness: Deleuze defines the field of transcendental empiricism as
"a pure a-subjective current of consciousness, an imperнsonal prereflexive consciousness,
a qualitative duration of consciousness without self."[3]
No wonder that (one of) his reference(s) here is the late Fichte, who tried to think the absolute
process of self-positing as a flow of Life beyond the opposites of subject and
object: "A life is the immanence of immanence, absolute immanence: it is sheer power, utter beatitude. Insofar as he overcomes the
aporias of the subject and the object Fichte, in his later philosophy, presents the
transcendental field as a life which does not depend on a Being and is not
subjected to an Act: an absolute immediate consciousness whose very activity no longer refers back to a being but ceaselessly posits itself
in a life."[4]
Perhaps
Jackson Pollock is the ultimate "Deleuzian painter": does his action-painting not directly
render this flow of pure becoming, the impersonal-unconscious life energy, the
encompassing field of virtuality out of which determinate paintings can
actualize themselves, this field of pure intensities with no meaning to be unearthed by interpretation? The
cult of Pollock's personality (heavy-drinking American macho) is secнondary with regard to this
fundamental feature: far from "expressing" his personality, his works
"sublate" or cancel it.[5]
The first example that comes to mind in the domain of cinema is Sergei Eisenstein: if his early
silent films are remembered primarily on account of their practice of montage in its different guises, from the
"montage of attractions" to "intellectual montage" (i.e.,
if their accent is on cuts), then his "mature" sound films shift the focus onto the
continuous proliferation of what Lacan called sinthomes, of the traces of affective intensities. Recall,
throughout both parts oilvan
the Terrible the motif of the thunderous explosion of rage that is continuously morphed and
thus assumes different guises, from the thunderstorm itself to the explosions of
uncontrolled fury. Although it may at first appear to be an expression of Ivan's psyche, its sound
detaches itself from
Ivan and starts to float around, passing from one to another person or to a
state not attributable to any diegetic person. This motif should be interpreted
not as an "allegory" with a fixed "deeper meanнing" but as a pure
"mechanic" intensity beyond meaning (this is what Eisenstein aimed at in his
idiosyncratic use of the term "operational").
[6]
Other such
motives echo and reverse each other, or, in what Eisenstein called "naked
transfer," jump from one to another expressive medium (say, when an
intensity gets too strong in the visual medium of mere shapes, it jumps and explodes in movementЧthen
in sound, or in color...). For
example, Kirstin Thompson points out how the motif of a single eye in Ivan is a
"floating motif," in itself strictly meaningless, but a repeated element that can,
according to context, acquire a range of expressive implications (joy,
suspicion, surveillance, quasi-godlike omнniscience).[6]
And the most interesting moments in Ivan occur when such motifs seem to explode their
preordained space. Not only do they acquire a multitude of ambiguous meanings no longer
covered by an encomнpassing
thematic or ideological agenda but also, in the most excessive moments, such a motif seems even
to have no meaning at all, instead just floating there as a provocation, as a
challenge to find the meaning that would tame its sheer provocative power.
Among
contemporary filmmakers, the one who lends himself ideally to a Deleuzian
reading is Robert Aitman, whose universe, best exemнplified by his masterpiece Short
Cuts, is effectively that of contingent encounters between a multitude of series, a
universe in which different series communicate and resonate at the level of what Aitman himself refers to as "subliminal
reality" (meaningless mechanic shocks, encounнters, and impersonal intensities that precede
the level of social meanнing).[7] So, in Nashville,
when violence explodes at the end (the murder of Barbara Jean at the concert), this explosion, although
unprepared and unaccounted
for at the level of the explicit narrative line, is nonetheless experienced as fully justified,
since the ground for it was laid at the level of signs circulating in the film's
"subliminal reality." And is it not that, when we hear the songs in Nashville,
Aitman directly mobilizes what Brian Massumi calls the "autonomy of affect"?[8]
That is to say, we totally misread Nashville if we locate the songs within the global
horizon of the ironico-critical
depiction of the vacuity and ritualized commercial alienнation of the universe of American
country music: on the contrary, we are allowed toЧeven seduced intoЧenjoy fully the
music on its own, in its affective intensity, independent of Altaian's obvious
critico-ideological project. (Incidentally, the same
goes for the songs from Brecht's great piecesЧtheir
musical pleasure is independent of their ideological mesнsage.)
[7]
What this
means is that one should also avoid the temptation of reducing Aitman to a poet of American alienation,
rendering the silent despair of everyday lives. There is another Aitman,
namely, the one of opening
oneself to joyful contigent encounters. Along the same lines as Deleuze and Guattari's reading of
Kafka's universe of the Absence of the inaccessible and elusive transcendent Center
(Castle, Court, God) as the Presence of multiple passages and transformations, one is tempted to read the Altmanian "despair
and anxiety" as the deceiving obverse of the more affirmative immersion into the multitude
of subliminal intensities. Of course, this underlying plane can also contain the obscene superego subtext of the
"official" ideological messageЧrecall the notorious "Uncle Sam" recruiting poster for
the U.S. Army:
This is an image whose demands, if not desires, seem absolutely clear, fo-cussed on a determinate object: it wants "you," that is, the young men of the proper age for military service. The immediate aim of the picture looks like a version of the Medusa effect: that is, it "hails" the viewer, verbally, and tries to transfix him with the directness of its gaze and (its most wonderful pictorial feature) the foreshortened pointing hand and finger that single out the viewer, accusing, designating, and commanding the viewer. But the desire to transfix is only a transitory and momentary goal. The longer-range motive is to move and mobilize the viewer, to send the beholder on to "the nearest recruiting station," and ultimately overseas to fight and possibly die for his country.
... Here the contrast with the German and Italian posters is clarifying. These are posters in which young soldiers hail their brothers, call them to the brotherhood of honorable death in battle. Uncle Sam, as his name indicates, has a more tenuous, indirect relation to the potential recruit. He is an older man who lacks the youthful vigor for combat, and perhaps even more important, lacks the direct blood connection that a figure of the fatherland would evoke. He asks young men to go fight and die in a war in which neither he nor his sons will participate. There are no "sons" of Uncle Sam.... Uncle Sam himself is sterile, a kind of abstract, pasteboard figure who has no body, no blood, but who impersonates the nation and calls for other men's sons to donate their bodies and their blood.
So what does
this picture want? A full analysis would take us deep into the political unconscious of a nation that is nominally
imagined as a disembodнied abstraction, an
Enlightenment polity of laws and not men, principles and not blood relationships, and actually embodied as a place where old white men send young men and women of all races
(including a disproporнtionately high number
of colored people) to fight their wars. What this real and imagined nation lacks is meatЧbodies and bloodЧand what it sends to obtain them is a hollow man, a meat supplier, or
perhaps just an artist.[9]
[8]
The first
thing to do here is to add to this series the famous Soviet poster
"Motherland is calling you," in which the interpellator is a mature
strong woman. We thus move
from the American imperialist Uncle through European Brothers to the Communist MotherЧhere
we have the split, constitutive
of interpellation, between law and superego (or want and desire). What a picture like this
wants is not the same as what it desires: while it wants us to participate in the noble struggle
for freedom, it desires blood, the
proverbial pound of our flesh (no wonder the elder sterile "Uncle [not Father] Sam" can be
deciphered as a Jewish figure, along
the lines of the Nazi reading of American military interventions: "the Jewish plutocracy wants the blood of
the innocent Americans to feed their
interests"). In short, it would be ridiculous to say that "Uncle Sam desires you": Uncle Sam wants you, but he
desires the partial object in you, your
pound of flesh. When a superego call WANTS (and enjoins) you to do it, to gather the strength and succeed, the
secret message of DESIRE is "I
know you will not be able to achieve it, so I desire you to fail and to gloat
in your failure!" This superego character, confirmed by the Yankee Doodle
association (recall the fact that superego figures inextricably mix obscene ferocity and clownish comedy), is
further sustained by the contradictory
character of its call: it first wants to arrest our movement and fixate our gaze, so that, surprised, we stare
at it; in a second moment, it wants us to follow its call and go to the nearest
conscription officeЧas if, after stopping us, it mockingly addresses us:
"Why do you stare at me like an
idiot? Didn't you get my point? Go to the nearest conscription post!" In
the arrogant gesture typical of the mocking characteristics of the superego, it laughs at our very act of taking
seriously its first call.[10]
When Eric
Santner told me about a game his father played with him when he was a small boy (the
father showed, opened up in front of him, his palm, in which there were a dozen or so
different coins; the father then closed his palm after a couple of seconds and
asked the boy how much money
there was in his palmЧif the small Eric guessed the exact sum, the father gave him the
money), this anecdote provoked in me an explosion of deep and uncontrollable
anti-Semitic satisfaction expressed in wild laughter: "You see, this is how Jews really teach their
children! Is this not a perfect case of your own theory of a proto-history
which accompanies the
explicit symbolic history? At the level of explicit history, your father was probably telling
you noble stories about Jewish suffering and the universal horizon of humanity, but his
true secret teaching was contained in those practical jokes about how to quickly deal with
money." Anti-Semitism
effectively is part of the ideologocal obscene underside ofа most of us.
[9]
And one finds a similar obscene
subtext even where one would not expect itЧin some texts that are commonly
perceived as feminist. To confront this obscene "plague of fantasies"
that persists at the level of "subliminal
reality" at its most radical, suffice it to (re)read Margaret Atwood's The Handmaid's Tale, the distopia
about the "Republic of Gilead,"
a new state on the East Coast of the United States that emerged when the Moral Majority took over. The ambiguity
of the novel is radical: its
"official" aim is, of course, to present as actually realized the
darkest conservative tendencies in
order to warn us about the threats of Christian fundamentalismЧthe evoked vision is expected to give rise to horror in
us. However, what strikes the eye is the utter fascination with this
imagнined universe and its invented
rules. Fertile woman are allocated to those privileged members of the new nomenklatura whose wives cannot bear childrenЧforbidden to read, deprived of their
names (they are called after the man
to whom they belong: the heroine is OffredЧ"of Fred"), they serve as
receptacles of insemination. The more we read the novel, the more it becomes clear that the fantasy we are
reading is not that of the Moral
Majority but that of feminist liberalism itself: an exact mirror imнage of the fantasies about the sexual degeneration
in our megalopolises that haunt members of the Moral Majority. So, what the
novel displays is desireЧnot of the Moral Majority but the hidden desire
of feminist liberalism itself.
The Becoming-Oedipal of
Deleuze
And back to
Deleuze, is the same violent sort of misreading as in the case of Hegel not also clearly
discernible in Deleuze's treatment of psychoanalнysis, with special regard to Lacan? What
Deleuze presents as "Oedipus" is a rather ridiculous simplification, if not
an outright falsification, of Lacan's position. In the last decades of Lacan's teaching, topics and
subнtitles like "au-dela de
l'Oedipe," TOedipe, un reve de Freud," and so forth abound; not only this, but Lacan even presents the very figure of
Oedipus at Colonus as a post-Oedipal figure, as a figure "beyond the
Oedipus complex." What, then, if one conceives of the Lacanian "obнverse of the Oedipus" as a kind of Deleuzian
"dark precursor" mediating between the two series, the
"official" Oedipal narrative of normalization, on the one side, and the presubjective field of
intensities and desiring machines, on
the other side? What if it is this that Deleuze desperately tries to
avoid, this "vanishing mediator" between the two series? What one
should do is thus to repeat, apropos of Deleuze's reductionist readнing
of (the Freudian) Oedipus (his other uncanny exception, in terms of a botched, simplistic interpretation), the same
gesture as the one that imposes itself in relation to Hegel.
In today's
theory, especially in cultural studies, reference to Oedipus is often reduced
to the extreme of a ridiculous straw man: the flat sceнnario of the drama of the child's entry into
normative heterosexuality. To fulfill this rhetorical function, the Oedipus complex has to be ascribed
a multitude of
inconsistent functions. Let me quote the following typical passage (which will tactfully be
allowed to remain anonymous):
[81]
"In the
Oedipal scenario, the young boy desires to conquer his mother sexually in order
to separate himself from her and begin to grow as an adult. For him to succeed, he must destroy
his father, his sexual competitor." So, it is not the father whose "castrating"
function is to separate the boy from his mother. In fact, the boy has to do three inconsistent things simulнtaneously:
conquer his mother, separate himself from her, and destroy his father. What Jerry Aline
Flieger did[11] is
something subversive in its properly Hegelian simplicity: she reinscribed-retranslated Oedipus back into Deleuzian territory,
(re)discovering in it an "abstract machine," a nomadic agent of
deterritorialization, the supreme case of what Deleuze and Guattari call the "lone wolf" who
stands for the limit of the pack of wolves, opening a "line of flight" toward its outside. And
effectively, does
OedipusЧthis stranger who blindly (in both senses of the term) followed his trajectoryЧnot stand
for the extreme limit of the pack of human wolves, by way of realizing, acting out, the utter limit of human experience, finishing alone (or,
rather, with a pack of exiles of his own) as, literally, a homeless nomad, a living dead among
humans? One should thus repeat
here the same operation as the one that, apropos of Hegel, enabled us to (re)discover in him
the philosopher who shows how neнcessity emerges out of contingency, the
philosopher of the vertiginous fluidity of concepts in which the subject is constantly displaced. The
conнcept that this
"Freudo-Lacanian buggery of Deleuze" should focus on is, predictably, that of the
phallus, the Deleuzian term for which is "dark precursor." Deleuze introduces it in Difference
and Repetition: "Thunderнbolts explode between different intensities, but they are preceded by an
invisible,
imperceptible dark precursor [precurseur sombre], which deнtermines their path in advance,
but in reverse, as though intagliated."[12]
As such, the dark
precursor is the signifier of a metadifference:
Given two heterogeneous series, two series of differences, the precursor plays the part of the differenciator of these differences. In this manner, by virtue of its own power, it puts them into immediate relation to one another: it is the in-itself of difference or the "differently different"Чin other words, difference in the second degree, the self-different which relates different to different by itself. Because the path it traces is invisible and becomes visible only in reverse, to the extent that it is traveled over and covered by the phenomenon it induces within the system, it has no place other than that from which it is "missing," no identity other than that which it lacks: it is precisely the object=x, the one which is "lacking in its place" as it lacks its own identity.[13]
[82]
Or as
Buchanan puts it in a concise way: "Dark precursors are those moments in a text which must be
read in reverse if we are not to mistake effects for causes."[14]
In The Logic of Sense, Deleuze develops this concept through a direct reference to
the Lacanian notion of "pure signifier"-. there has to be a short circuit between the two
series, that of the signifier and that of the signified, for the effect-of-sense to take place. This
short circuit is what Lacan
calls the "quilting point," the direct inscription of the signifier into the order of the
signified in the guise of an "empty" signifier without signified. This
signifier represents the (signifying) cause within the order of its effects, thus subverting the (mis)perceived
"natural" order within which the
signifier appears as the effect/expression of the signified.
And
effectively, the relationship of Deleuze to the field generally desнignated as that of
"structuralism" is much more ambiguous than it may appear. Not only
is the key notion of "dark precursor" in The Logic of Sense directly developed in Lacanian
structuralist terms; at the same time, Deleuze wrote "A quoi reconnait-on le
structuralisme?" a brief, concise, and sympathetic account that, precisely, presents structuralism not as the thought of fixed transcendent Structures
regulating the flux of expeнriences,
but as deploying a consistent theory of the role of nonsense as the generator of the flux of sense.[15]
Furthermore, Deleuze here explicitly refers to (and develops in detail) the
Lacanian identification of this signifier as phallus.[16]
How, then, are we to read his later obvious "hardening" of the stance
toward "structuralism?" Why is the very Lacanian reference of the "dark precursor" reduced to the
status of a "dark precursor" in the later Deleuze's thought, turned into a kind of "vanishing
mediator" whose traces are to be
erased in the finished result?
Perhaps it is
all too hasty to dismiss Deleuze's endorsement of "strucнturalism" as a feature
belonging to an epoch when he was not yet fully aware of all the consequences of his basic
position (thus, the "hardenнing" would be conceived of as a necessary radicalization). What if
this hardening is, on the contrary, a sign of "regression," of a false
"line of flight,"
a false way out of a certain deadlock that resolves it by sacrificing its complexity?
[83]
This,
perhaps, is why Deleuze experienced his collaboration with Guattari as such a "relief":
the fluidity of his texts cowritten with Guattari, the sense that now, finally,
things run smoothly, is effectively a fake reliefЧit signals that the burden of thinking was
successfully avoided. The
true enigma is hence: why does Deleuze succumb to this strange urge to "demonize"
structuralism, disavowing his own roots in it (on account of which one can effectively
claim that Deleuze's attack on "structuralism" is enacted on behalf of what he got from
structuralism, that it is strictly inherent to
structuralism)? Again, why must he deny this
link?
Is the Freudian Oedipus complex
(especially in terms of its Lacanian
interpretive appropriation) not the exact opposite of the reduction of the multitude of social intensities onto the
mother-father-and-me matrix: the
matrix of the explosive opening up of the subject onto the social space? Undergoing "symbolic
castration" is a way for the subject to be thrown out of the family
network, propelled into a wider social networkЧOedipus,
the operator of deterritorialization. However, what about the fact that, nonetheless, Oedipus
"focuses" the initial "polymorphous perversity" of drives
onto the mother-father-and-me coordinates? More precisely, is "symbolic castration" not also the name
for a process by means of which the
child-subject enters the order of sense proper, of the ABSTRACTION of sense, gaining the capacity to
abstract a quality from its
embeddedness in a bodily Whole, to conceive of it as a becoming no longer attributed to a certain substanceЧas Deleuze
would have put it, "red"
no longer stands for the predicate of the red thing but for the pure flow of
becoming-red? So, far from tying us down to our bodily reality, "symbolic castration" sustains our very
ability to "transcend" this realнity and enter the space of
immaterial Becoming. Does the autonomous smile that survives on its own
when the cat's body disappears in Alice in
Wonderland also not stand for an
organ "castrated," cut off from the body? What if, then, phallus
itself, as the signifier of castration, stands for such an organ without a
body?
Is this not a
further argument for the claim that Deleuze's quasi cause is his name for the Lacanian
"phallic signifier"? Recall how, according to Deleuze, the quasi cause "extracts
singularities from the present, and from individuals and persons which occupy this
present,"[17] and, in the
same movement, provides
them with their relative autonomy with regard to the intensive processes as their real causes,
endowing these impassive and sterile effects with their morphogenetic powerЧis this double movement not exactly that of "symbolic
castration" (whose signifier is phallus)?
[84]
First, the
impassive-sterile Event is cut off, extracted, from its virile, corporeal, causal base (if
"castrations" means anything at all, it means this). Then, this flow of Sense-Event is
constituted as an autonomous field of its own, the autonomy of the incorporeal symbolic order with regard
to its corporeal embodiments. "Symbolic castration," as the
elementary operation of the quasi cause, is thus a profoundly materialist concept,
since it answers the
basic need of any materialist analysis: "If we are to get rid of essentialist and
typological thought we need some process through which virtual multiplicities are derived from
the actual world and some process through which the results of this derivation maybe given enough coherence and autonomy."[18]
The problem,
of course, is the following one: the minimal actualization is here conceived as the
actualization of the virtual, after its extraction from the preceding actual. Is, then, every actual the result of
the actualization of the preceding virtual (so that the same goes for the
actual out of which the actualized virtual
was extracted), or is there an actual that precedes the virtual, since every virtual has to be extracted from some actual? Perhaps the way out of this
predicamentЧis the virtual extracted
from the actual as its impassive-sterile effect or is it the productive process that generates the actual?Чis the
ultimate, absolute identity of the
two operations, an identity hinted at by Deleuze himself when he described the
operation of the "pseudo cause" as that of visualization (extraction
of the virtual) and, simultaneously, minimal actualization (the pseudo cause confers on the virtual a minimum
of ontological conнsistency). What
if, as we know from Schelling, what makes from the field of potentialities an actual reality is not the
addition of some raw realнity (of
matter) but, rather, the addition of pure ideality (of logos)7. Kant
himself was already aware of this
paradox: the confused field of impresнsions
turns into reality when supplemented by the transcendental Idea. What this
fundamental lesson of transcendental idealism means is that virtualization and actualization are two sides of
the same coin: actuality constitutes
itself when a VIRTUAL (symbolic) supplement is added to the pre-ontological
real. In other words, the very extraction of the virtual from the real ("symbolic castration")
constitutes realityЧactual reality is the real filtered through the virtual.
The function
of the quasi cause is therefore inherently contradictory. Its task is, at one and the same
time, to perform a push toward actualнization (endowing multiplicities with a
minimum of actuality) and to counter actualization by way of extracting virtual events from the corporeal processes that are their
causes. One should conceive of these two aspects as identical.
[85]
The properly
Hegelian paradox at work here is that the only way for a virtual state to actualize itself is to be
supplemented by another
virtual feature. (Again, recall Kant: how is a confused multiplicity of subjective sensations
transformed into "objective" reality? It happens when the subjective
function of transcendental synthesis is added to this multiplicity.) This
is the "phallic" dimension at its most elementary: the excess of the virtual that
sustains actualization. And, this reference to the phallic signifier also enables us to answer one of the standard
reproaches to the Lacanian notions of phallus
and castration: the idea that they inнvolve
a kind of ahistorical short circuit, that is to say, the complaint that they directly link the limitation serving as a
condition of human existence as such
to a particular threat (that of castration) that relies on a specific patriarchal gender constellation. The next move
is, then, usually the one of trying
to get rid of the notion of castrationЧthis "ridiculous" Freudian
claimЧby way of claiming that the threat of castration is, at its best, just a
local expression of the global limitation of the human condition, which is that of human finitude, experienced in a whole
series of constraints (the existence
of other people who limit our freedom, our mortality, and, also, the necessity to "choose one's sex").
Such a move from castration to an
anxiety grounded in the very finitude of the human condition is, of course, the standard existential-philosophical
move of "saving" Freud by way of getting rid of the
embarrassing topic of castration and penis envy
("Who can take this seriously today?"). Psychoanalysis is thus reнdeemed,
magically transformed into a respectable academic discipline that deals with how suffering human subjects cope
with the anxieties of finitude. The
(in)famous advice given to Freud by Jung when their boat approached the coast of the United States in 1912
(that Freud should leave out or at
least limit the accent on sexuality to render psychoanalysis more acceptable to the American medical establishment)
is resuscitated here. Why is it not sufficient
to emphasize how "castration" is just a particular instance of the general limitation of the
human condition? Or, to put it in a slightly different way, how should one
insist on the link between the universal symbolic structure and the particular
corporeal economy? The old reproach
against Lacan is that he conflates two levels, the allegedly
neutral-universal-formal symbolic structure and the particular-gendered-bodily references; say, he emphasizes
that the phallus is not the penis as an organ but as a signifier, even a
"pure" signifierЧso, why then call this "pure" signifier "phallus"? As it was
clear to Deleuze (and not only to
Lacan), the notion of castration answers a very specific question: how does the universal symbolic process detach itself
from its corporeal roots? How does it emerge in its relative autonomy?
"Castration" designates the violent
bodily cut that enables us to enter the domain of the incorporeal.
[86]
And, the same
goes for the topic of fmitude: "castration" is not simply one of the local cases of the
experience of finitudeЧthis concept tries to answer a more fundamental "arche-transcendental" question,
namely, how do we, humans, experience
ourselves as marked by finitude in the first
place? This fact is not
self-evident: Heidegger was right to emphasize that only humans exist in the mode of
"being-towards-death." Of course, animals are also somehow
"aware" of their limitation, of their limited power, and so forthЧthe hare does try to escape the fox.
And yet, this is not the same as
human finitude, which emerges against the backнground of the small child's narcissistic attitude of illusory
omnipotence (of course, we do indeed
say that, in order to become mature, we have to accept our limitations).
What lurks behind this narcissistic attitude is,
however, the Freudian death drive, a kind of "undead" stubbornness denounced already by Kant as a violent excess
absent in animals, which is why, for
Kant, only humans need education through discipline. The symbolic Law does not tame and regulate nature
but, precisely, applies itself to an
unnatural excess. Or, to approach the same complex from another direction: at its most radical, the
helplessness of the small child about which Freud speaks is not physical
helplessness, the inability to provide for one's needs, but a helplessness in
the face of the enigma of the
Other's desire, the helpless fascination with the excess of the Other's enjoyment, and the ensuing inability to account
for it in the available terms of meaning.
When Roman
Jakobson wrote on phonemes and the bodily grounding of language, he focused on the crucial gap
between embodied gestures and the free-floating symbolic network of
phonemesЧthis gap is what Lacan calls "castration." Jakobson's
crucial point is that it is only the SIGNIFIER, not meaning, that can do this job of deterritorialization:
meaning tends to revert to our concrete life-world embeddedness (the premodern
antropomorphic mirroring of interior and exterior is the atнtitude of meaning par
excellence.) So, the phallus, far from signalling the rootedness of the symbolic in our bodily
experience (its territorializa-tion), is the "pure signifier" and, as such, the very agent of
deterritorialization.
Here, Jakobson introduces the key dialectical notion of secondary grounding in bodily experience:
yes, our language shows overall traces of this embodiment (the word
"locomotive" resembles the profile of an old steam locomotive; the word
"front" is formed in the front of our oral cavity, and the word "back" in the
back of itЧand so on and so forth). However, all of these are reterritorializations against the background
of the fundamental cut that is the condition of meaning.[19]
This is why the anthropomorphic
model of mirroring between language and the human
[87]
аbody, the reference to the body as a fundamental
frame of reference for our understanding, is to be abandonedЧlanguage is "inhuman."
(The аprocess thus has three phases: (1) primordial territorialization as the
"assemblage of bodies"Чan organism marks its suroundings, its exchanges with it, in a texture of
affective inscriptions, tatoos, and so forth;
(2)
deterritorializationЧpassage to the
immaterial, virtual production of senseЧmarks are freed from
their origins (enunciator, reference);
(3)
reterritorializationЧwhen
language turns into a medium of communication, pinned down to its subject of enunciation whose thoughts it expresses, to the reality it
designates.)
[1]
'The genealogy of Deleuze's
concepts is often strange and unexpectedЧsay, his assertion of the Anglo-Saxon notion of external relations is
clearly indebted to the religious problematic of grace. The missing link here is Alfred Hitchcock, the
English Catholic, in whose films a change in relations between persons,
in no way rooted in their characters, totally external to them, changes
everything, deeply affects them (say, when, at the beginning of North-by-Norlhwest,
Thornhill is wrongly identified as Kaplan). Chabrol and Rohmer's Catholic
reading of Hitchcock (in their Hitchcock,
1954) deeply influenced Deleuze since, in the Jansenist tradition, it
focuses precisely on "grace' as a contingent divine intervention that has
nothing to do with the inherent virtues and qualities of the affected
characters.
[2] And is this ambiguity not homologous to the ontological paradox of quantum physics? The very "hard reality" that emerges out of the fluctuation through the collapse of the wave-function, is the outcome of observation, that is, of the intervention of consciousness. Consciousness is thus not the domain of potentiality, multiple options, and so forth, as opposed to hard single realityЧ reality previous to its perception is fluid-multiple-open, and conscious perception reduces this spectral, preontological multiplicity to one ontologically, fully constituted, reality.
[3] Cilles Deleuze, "Immanence: une vie..." quoted from John Marks, GiilesDeleuze (London: Pluto Press, 1998), p. 29.
[4] Deleuze, op. tit., p. 30. One is tempted to oppose to this Deleuzian absolute immanence of the flow of Life, as the presubjective consciousness, the Freudo-Lacanian unconscious subject ($) as the agency of the death drive.
[5] So what about the opposition Pollock-Rothko? Does it not correspond to the opposition of Deleuze versus Freud/Lacan? The virtual field of potentialities versus the minimal difference, the gap between background and figure?
[6]
See Kirstin Thompson, Eisenstein's
"Ivan the Terrible": A Neoformalist Analysis (Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press, 1981)
[7] See Robert T. Self, Robert All/nan's Subliminal Reality (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2002).
[8] See Brian Massumi, "The Autonomy of Affect," in Delenzc: A Critical Reader, edited by Paul Patton (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996).
[9] Tom Mitchell, "What Do Pictures Km//;'Want?" October, no. 77 (summer 1996): 64-66.
[10] What, then, more generally, does a picture want? One is tempted to apply here the good old Lacanian triad of ISR: at the level of the Imaginary, it is a lure that wants to seduce us into aesthetic pleasure; at the level ot the Symbolic, it calls for its interpretation; at the level of the Real, it endeavors to shock us, to cause us to avert our eyes or to fixate our gaze.
[11] See Jerry Aline Flieger, "Overdetermined Oedipus," in A Deleuzutit Century? edited by Ian Buchanan (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 1999).
[12] Cilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), p. 1 19.
[13] Deleuze, op. cit., pp. 119-20.
[14] Ian Buchanan, Deleuzism (Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2000), p. 5.
[15] Gilles Deleuze, "A quoi reconnait-on le structuralisme?" in Histoirc de la philosophic, \ol. 8: Lc XXeme slide, edited by Francois Chatelet (Paris: Hachelte, 1972), pp. 299-335 (written in 1967); English translation, "How Do We Recognize Structuralism?" published as an appendix in Charles). Stivale, The Two-Fold Thought ofDeleuzc and Guattari (New York: Guilford Press, 1998!, pp. 258-82. And one is tempted to claim that Deleuze's turn against Hegel is, in a homologous way, a turn against his own originsЧrecall one of Deleuze's early texts, his deeply sympathetic review of Hyppolite's reading of Hegel's Logic, reprinted in Jean Hyppolite, Logic and hvisW'''* (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997), pp. 191-95
[16] See Stivale, op. cit., pp. 277-78. Por a more detailed account of the link between "dark precursor and phallus, see 77k' Logic ol Seme, pp. 227Ч30.
[17] Deleuze, 7/u' Logic of Seme, p. )0>h
[18] DeLanda, op. cit., p. 115.